18 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Mark A. Michael [18]Mark Alan Michael [2]
  1.  24
    Is Nonanthropocentrism Anti-Democratic?Mark Alan Michael - 2020 - Environmental Values 29 (1):9-28.
    Environmental pragmatists such as Ben Minteer and Bryan Norton have argued that there is an anti-democratic strain to be found in the work of some nonanthropocentrists. I examine three possible sources of the pragmatists' concern: the claim that nonanthropocentrists know the political truth, the claim that those who disagree with their basic principle should be excluded from discussions of policy and the claim that their basic principle is self-evident. I argue here that none of these claims are objectionably anti-democratic when (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  11
    Liberalism, Environmentalism, and the Principle of Neutrality.Mark A. Michael - 2000 - Public Affairs Quarterly 14 (1):39-56.
  3.  39
    The Problem with Methodological Pragmatism.Mark A. Michael - 2012 - Environmental Ethics 34 (2):135-157.
    Methodological pragmatists argue that, given the dire state of the environment, the primary goal of environmentalists, including philosophers who work in environmental ethics, must be to work together to ensure that environmentally friendly policies are put into place. They must set aside their differences and not argue over their competing theoretical justifications of environmental policies, as that contributes to divisiveness among environmentalists and prevents this cooperation from occurring. The proposal to ignore disagreements over theory gets cashed out in three distinct (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  44
    Utilitarianism and Retributivism: What's the Difference?Mark A. Michael - 1992 - American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (2):173 - 182.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  36
    To Swat or Not to Swat.Mark A. Michael - 1996 - Environmental Ethics 18 (2):165-180.
    A central thesis of biocentrism is that all living things have intrinsic value. But when conflicts arise between the interests of humans and other organisms, this claim often has counterintuitive consequences. It would be wrong, for example, to swat pesky flies. Some biocentrists have responded by positing a taxonomy of interests in which human interests justifiably supersede those of other living things. I express doubts about whether this maneuver can succeed, and suggest that even if it does, it then commits (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  16
    Is there a duty to accept punishment?Mark A. Michael - 1993 - Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (2):200-223.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  9
    Current periodical articles 897.Mark A. Michael - 1991 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (4).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  38
    Environmental Egalitarianism and 'Who do you Save?' Dilemmas.Mark A. Michael - 1997 - Environmental Values 6 (3):307 - 325.
    Some critics have understood environmental egalitarianism to imply that human and animal lives are generally equal in value, so that killing a human is no more objectionable than killing a dog. This charge should be troubling for anyone with egalitarian sympathies. I argue that one can distinguish two distinct versions of equality, one based on the idea of equal treatment, the other on the idea of equally valuable lives. I look at a lifeboat case where one must choose between saving (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Fraser Cowley, Metaphysical Delusion Reviewed by.Mark A. Michael - 1992 - Philosophy in Review 12 (3):174-176.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  21
    Hugh P. McDonald, ed. Pragmatism and Environmentalism.Mark A. Michael - 2015 - Environmental Ethics 37 (1):119-120.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  43
    How to Interfere with Nature.Mark A. Michael - 2001 - Environmental Ethics 23 (2):135-154.
    The principle that we should not interfere with nature plays a prominent role in both popular and academic accounts of environmental ethics. For example, it is often cited to justify the claims that we should not actively manage wilderness areas and that we should not extinguish naturally occurring fires in those areas. It is far from clear, however, exactly what that principle entails for our treatment of species and ecosystems. Does all human interaction with nature amount to interference? If there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  17
    How to Interfere with Nature.Mark A. Michael - 2001 - Environmental Ethics 23 (2):135-154.
    The principle that we should not interfere with nature plays a prominent role in both popular and academic accounts of environmental ethics. For example, it is often cited to justify the claims that we should not actively manage wilderness areas and that we should not extinguish naturally occurring fires in those areas. It is far from clear, however, exactly what that principle entails for our treatment of species and ecosystems. Does all human interaction with nature amount to interference? If there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  55
    Is it natural to drive species to extinction?Mark A. Michael - 2005 - Ethics and the Environment 10 (1):49-66.
    : Whether or not extinction caused by human activities is natural depends on which sense of the term 'natural' is under consideration. Given one sense of that term which has some grip on the popular imagination, it is. This suggests that at a minimum environmentalists should be very careful about invoking 'the natural' and related concepts such as 'acting naturally' when they propose moral principles. I argue here for the stronger claim that the 'natural' is either redundant and serves to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  28
    International Justice and Wilderness Preservation.Mark A. Michael - 1995 - Social Theory and Practice 21 (2):149-176.
  15.  40
    Redistributive Taxation, Self‐Ownership and the Fruit of Labour.Mark A. Michael - 1997 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 14 (2):137–146.
    Libertarians such as Nozick have argued that any redistributive tax scheme intended to achieve and maintain an egalitarian distributive pattern will violate self‐ownership. Furthermore, since self‐ownership is a central component of the idea of freedom, instituting an egalitarian distribution makes a society less rather than more free. All this turns on the claim, accepted by both libertarians and their critics, that a redistributive tax will violate self‐ownership because it must expropriate the fruit of a person’s labour. I show here that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  36
    To Swat or Not to Swat.Mark A. Michael - 1996 - Environmental Ethics 18 (2):165-180.
    A central thesis of biocentrism is that all living things have intrinsic value. But when conflicts arise between the interests of humans and other organisms, this claim often has counterintuitive consequences. It would be wrong, for example, to swat pesky flies. Some biocentrists have responded by positing a taxonomy of interests in which human interests justifiably supersede those of other living things. I express doubts about whether this maneuver can succeed, and suggest that even if it does, it then commits (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  12
    What's in a Name? Pragmatism, Essentialism, and Environmental Ethics.Mark A. Michael - 2003 - Environmental Values 12 (3):361-379.
    Essentialists like J. Baird Callicott have argued that one cannot have an environmental ethic unless one adopts the nonanthropocentric principle, which holds that things other than humans can be morally considerable in their own right, typically because they are thought to be intrinsically valuable. Pragmatists like Bryan Norton reject this; they claim that environmental ethics has no core or essence, and hence that the nonanthropocentric principle is not essential to an environmental ethic. Norton advances as an alternative the Convergence Hypothesis, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  44
    Why not interfere with nature?Mark A. Michael - 2002 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5 (1):89-112.
    Advocates of an environmental ethic frequently claim that what makes an ethical theory truly and uniquely environmental is its commitment to the principle that environmental wholes such as species, ecosystems, and biotic communities are morally considerable. The prevailing view is that our primary duty towards these wholes is to respect their integrity, stability, and beauty, and that the best way to do this is to leave them alone, not interfere with them, and let nature follow its own course. But is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark